Zorn’s lemma

An chain is a subset of a partial order in which any two elements are comparable (basically, a totally ordered subset). Zorn’s lemma is equivalent to the axiom of choice.

Theorem 1(Zorn's Lemma).

Let be any partially ordered set such that every chain has an upper bound. Then, has a maximal element.

A maximal element has no element greater or equal to it. It is NOT greater that or equal to every element in the set.


Properties of infinite cardinals

Theorem 2.

For all either , .

Proof
Let and . Assume and are infinite, since the finite case is easily handled.

Define .

is a partial order, with if and , i.e, .

Let be any chain in . Let

Clearly, is well defined, and is injective. Thus, is an upper bound for . By Zorn’s lemma, has a maximal element , , , injective.

If , we are done, since we have found an injection from to , i.e, .
Suppose (proper subset), and is a proper subset of . Then, we can contradict the maximality of by extending it in a basic manner. If , we have found a surjection from to , so .

Theorem 3.

Let and be any infinite sets.

  • .

We will need the following theorem:

Theorem 4.

Every infinite set has a disjoint covering of countable sets.

Coming up in the next lecture.


More cardinal arithmetic

The cardinality of is denoted by . The cardinality of the reals is denoted by . We know that the cardinality of and the interval is the same (several bijections exist, like the stereographic projection of a unit circle onto the real line, or the sigmoid function). Also, the cardinality of is the same as the cardinality of (set of all binary sequences). Thus, the cardinality of is .

Now, several non-trivial conclusions can be drawn using cardinal arithmetic.

  • . Now, . Thus, .
  • Similarly, since , we have , and .
  • That is about as far as we can stretch it, since Cantor’s Theorem forces the cardinality of the power set of to be greater than .
  • .

Interesting note: while the set of all functions from to has cardinality , the set of all continuous functions from to has cardinality . This is because a continuous function is fully determined by the values it takes on a dense subset of its domain (Rudin, 4.4 page=3). So the cardinality of the set is equal to , and hence to .