Assignment 1

1

FTSOC, assume is a finite dimensional vector space over . By definition, this implies that has a finite spanning set , i.e, for all , . Now, . But, , due to Cantor’s theorem. Thus, is not a finite dimensional vector space over .

2

For each Y, draw line segments connecting the outward tips to form a triangle. Note that the Y divides the triangle into 3 triangles. Pick a point, , in each triangle (this is possible since is dense in ). Associate the Y with the set . If any two Ys have are associated with the same set of rational points, they must intersect. Thus, no two Ys are associated with the same set of rational points. Thus, if is the set of all Ys on the plane, then , i.e, we can only place countably many Ys on the plane.

3

Consider the set . Note that . Thus, . Pick . Now, , because otherwise we would have for .

4

Assume there exists such a set . consider two points and of . For each , draw a circle of radius centered at , and another centered at . Let be the set of all intersection points between the two circles. The cardinality of is . Note that any other point of must be in .

5

Zorn’s Lemma: In a partial order, if every chain has an upper bound, then there exists a maximal element.

Axiom of Choice: For any set X of nonempty sets, there exists a choice function f that is defined on X and maps each set of X to an element of that set.

Set be a collection of non empty sets. Let be the set of all functions defined on a subset of such that . We know that is non empty, since we can always define on a finite subset of . Define a partial order on by if . Consider a chain in . Let . The domain of is a union of subsets of , and hence is a subset of . is well defined, since for each in the domain of , for some , and being a chain forces for all whenever is defined. Additionally, . Thus, , and every chain has an upper bound. From Zorn’s lemma, there must exist a maximal element in . If the domain of is not , it can be trivially extended to contradict the maximality of . Thus, the domain of is . Since , it satisfies the properties of a choice function.

6

Let be an infinite graph. Partition as where is the set of all points with finite neighborhoods and is the set of all points with infinite neighborhoods.

If , we can construct an infinite independent set: Pick , , , and so on. If we run out of elements at any point, it would mean is a finite union of finite sets, which is not possible.

If is finite, must be infinite. Pick , and consider as an infinite subgraph of . We can again partition . If is infinite, we can construct an infinite independent set in , which will also be an infinite independent set of . If is finite and is infinite, we pick and consider as an infinite subgraph of . In this process, if we for some have to be finite, we can construct an independent set. If is never finite for all , we get a sequence of points , which form an infinite connected graph since and and so on.

7

Suppose is an infinite graph that is not properly -colorable for any positive integer . It follows from the De Bruijn–Erdős theorem that for every positive integer , has a finite subgraph which is not colorable. is a countable subgraph of which is not colorable for any positive integer .

8

Let α ≤ β be two infinite cardinals and let |B| = β. An α-covering of
B is a collection of pairwise disjoint sets {Ai | i ∈ I} such that |Ai| = α
for each i ∈ I and B = ⋃
i∈I Ai. Does B have an α-covering? Justify
answer with proof.

Define . We know that is non empty, since subsets of of cardinality have the trivial covering.
Define a partial order by if and .

Let be any chain in .
.
For all , either , or vice versa.
Let and . It is easy to see that is a -covering for . , so Zorn’s lemma is applicable. Let be the maximal element.

If , we are done.
If is a proper subset of , two cases:

  • : Change the covering by appending the elements in to some . Does not create a contradiction.
  • : you can take a subset of cardinality of and add it to , contradicting the maximality of .

9

Bijective proof: We have to choose things from things, labeled . We can choose to either pick , or choose not to. In the latter case, we would have to pick things from , which can be done in ways. If we chose to include , we are next faced with the question of whether to include . If we do not include , we will have to choose the remaining things from , the number of ways to do that being . If we include , we then have to look at the cases of being included and not being included. Continuing with this iterative process, we get

Computational proof:
We know that

If we rewrite as , we see that , and , and so on.

10


Let the number of subsets of size congruent to 0, 1, and 2 mod 3 be , , and respectively. Then, we have . Also,

So, . Additionally, . Thus, we have

Combining with , we have


Again, . Here, . Hence, . Also,

So,


Here, . .

So


Again, . But, .